The
ontological argument :A critique
The
ontological argument is designed to logically prove God's existence; hence it
is possible to disagree with the argument,
even if you do believe in God. I think this argument does NOT prove God's
existence because the first premise is
not strong enough and the second is just wrong. It cannot be applied in this
case as it contradicts Anslem's
very definition of God.
The
ontological argument: A summary
Anslem's
argument is based on his definition of god as "something than which nothing
greater can be thought" and his three
premises, such that:
Premise 1:
God exists at least in our understanding
Premise 2:
Existing in reality is better than existing in understanding
Premise 3: it
is possible to think of God existing in reality
Then the
argument might be paraphrased as :
1. God does
NOT exist in reality (Assumption for an indirect derivation)
2. God exists
at least in our understanding (Premise 1)
3. Therefore
God exists only in our understanding (from 1 and 2)
4. Existing
in reality is better than existing only in understanding (Premise 2)
5. It is
possible to think of God existing in reality (Premise 3)
(That is
there is no logical contradiction in thinking that god exists in reality.)
6. Therefore,
it is possible to think of God to be better than God is. (From 4, and 5)
(Because if
something exists only in our understanding but it is possible for something to
exist in reality,
then it is
possible for that thing to be better than it is. )
7. God is the
greatest being that can be thought of. (by definition)
8. Since 6
and 7 contradict each other, it means that the assumption in 1 must be wrong,
therefore the
opposite must
be true, hence god does exist in reality.
My Critique:
The way it
stands, this argument can be proven invalid by:
1) Showing
that the premises are false or
2)
Constructing another invalid argument that has the exact same form as this
argument, or
The second
attack; that of constructing a counter example has already been stated by Gaunilo, in his
reply on
behalf of the fool, where Gaunilo applies the same set of steps to prove the
existence of a lost island greater than
which cannot be thought of.
My objection
to the argument stems from the fact that the first two premises are less than
certain, and that they do not
apply to the present case in particular.
Problems with
Premise 1 (God exists at least in our understanding):
To Anselm
something exists in our understanding if we are able to think of it, to have a
concept of it. He draws the
distinction between something existing in thought and existing in real by using
the example of a painting existing in
the painter's [imagination] understanding even before he paints it, and once
he is done paining it, it exists in
reality too.
He says that
even the fool can understand the definition of god as that than which a greater
cannot be thought, just by
hearing these words. (page 1) Thus Anselm gets his first premise that god exists
at least in our understanding.
But later,
Anselm draws a distinction; he says that there must be more than one way in
which something is thought; to think a thing is to think the word that signifies that thing. But in
another sense, it is to understand what exactly
the thing is. (pages 2 and 3) That to merely hear the name of something and
thus it existing in your understanding,
for example hearing of Santa Claus; is different from actually knowing and understanding
what Santa Claus
is.
He says No
one who understands what God is can think that god does not exist (page 3).
To me at least, it is not clear which
kind of understanding he is using as the premise in his argument. Is he talking
about a) god's existence in
the understanding of the fool or b) god's existence in the understanding of
the NOT fool
a) god's
existence in the understanding of the fool:
If I am a representative sample of
the fools then I can say that God
can only exist as a name in the fool's understanding, but not as the concept
per definition.
For as soon
as I think of something as great as I can make it, I right away can think of
something better,
so I can
think of things than which greater things CAN be thought of, but I can never
think of this one
thing that is
maximum and complete perfection to which I cannot add anything to make it
better. Thus I
cannot think
of God and thus God does not exist at least in my understanding.
OR
b) god's
existence in the understanding of the NOT fool:
Then Anselm
must be talking of God existing at least in the understanding of the not
fool the one who
'understand[s]
what exactly the thing is'. But this makes his argument for proving his
premise circular and thus weaker. For
someone to understand exactly what the thing is, it presupposes that, that
thing already exists in their
understanding. It does not prove the existence, of that thing in their understanding. Instead, it follows from the said existence.
For e.g. to actually understand what santa claus is, santa claus must first
exist in your understanding,
and then you would understand what he is.
So I think
that the first premise is not the strongest, but even if I were to accept it,
the second one breaks his argument
anyways.
Problems with
Premise 2 (Existing in reality is better than existing in understanding):
At a first
glance it looks almost reasonable, but then, I canΓÇÖt answer the question why?
Why would existence make
something better? May be it is a valid claim as applied to some things, like
cupcakes, but definitely not valid when
applied to ideas that are already complete in themselves, like perfection or
infinity.
For example,
the infinity on the number line, only exists in our understanding, there is no
real number that is infinite,
however there exists an implicit infinity in the fraction 1/3 which can be
written as a non-terminating decimal
0.3333….
Now saying that if infinity exists in real it is a better infinity
than the infinity that exists in our understanding
would be wrong. There is no question of infinity becoming qualitatively better
merely by existing in real. It
is as good or as bad as it is, whether in real or in our understanding. Another
example would be the idea of
wanting to add something to infinity to make it even more infinite. By
definition, infinity is endless. You cannot add
something to infinity to make it even more endless. It is already endless.
Similarly if
we accept the definition that god is complete perfection then, how would his
existence add to his perfection?
He IS already perfect, it is done, mission accomplished, if his existence can
make him 'more prefect' then it means
he was not perfect to begin with, thus contradicting the definition.
Therefore, it
is wrong to use this premise for God. It should only be used for things that
CAN be made better. By using it for
the already 'best' things we will always arrive at a contradiction and thus
can prove anything.
Conclusion:
Based on the
above objections to the premises, I think the ontological argument, however
well intended, does not prove
god's existence.
No comments:
Post a Comment